Authors: RENÉ GIRARD
-252-
on Dionysus, begging him to bring back real vengeance as a cure for what seemed to him the
worst of all possible fates,
ressentiment
.
Such frivolity could flourish only in our privileged centuries, in privileged parts of the world
where real vengeance had retreated so much that its terror had become unintelligible. But
sincere prayers are never in vain, and the prayers of those who desired the return of
vengeance have finally been heard.
Real vengeance is back among us in the shape of nuclear and other absolute weapons,
reducing our planet to the size of a global primitive village, terrified one again by the
possibility of unlimited blood feud. Real vengeance is so awesome that even the most
vengeful men do not dare to unleash it, knowing perfectly well that all the dreadful things
they can do unto their enemies, their enemies can also do unto them.
Compared to this,
ressentiment
and other nineteenth-century annoyances pale to
insignificance, or rather their only significance is the increasing rage everywhere that turns
ressentiment
back into irrepressible vengeance and can unleash the unspeakable.
At more and more levels of reality, the urgency of the Gospel message can no longer be
disregarded with impunity. Those thinkers who, like Nietzsche, unthinkingly appealed to real
vengeance in their itch to get rid of
ressentiment
resemble these foolish characters in fairy
tales who make the wrong wish and come to grief when it comes true.
This can be interpreted as a warning of sorts. But this warning can and is disregarded with
impunity by almost everybody. Most people go on spouting nineteenth-century ideas as if the
return of real vengeance in our world were not an accomplished fact. The truth is that, for the
time being at least, real vengeance has a power of dissuasion such that, concretely, nothing
has changed. The very enormity of the threat protects us from the threatened violence.
Ressentiment
is intense enough to generate more and more intellectual nihilism but not
intense enough so far to annihilate real being.
Real vengeance has not yet concretely demonstrated its power upon our lives and it never
will, in a sense, because if it did, there would be no more lives to be affected by anything.
There would be no one left to acknowledge the return of absolute vengeance as the real event
of our time.
As a result one can go on thinking frivolously and pretending today that Nietzsche makes
sense as a teacher of ethics, or of history, or as a philosopher, or as a guide for some kind of
"lifestyle," or whatever. This cannot fail to sound more futile and unreal with each passing year. The price to be paid for this is the price any historical era must pay for avoiding its real
issues, a certain barrenness of the spirit and a growing sterility in all its "cultural activities."
Our military men love to give mythological names to their nuclear
-253-
missiles, Pluto, Poseidon, Ariadne, and the like. Too bad they never resorted to Dionysus
himself, but it really does not matter. Those who understand do not need such literalness and
it would not make any impression on those who do not understand. The contemporary use of
mythology is more profound that all the mythological games of our philosophers since the
Renaissance.
Even though Nietzsche had ceased writing long before his espousal of mythological violence
began to reveal its frivolous side, there was something in him that fiercely resisted his own
wager. When studying "Dionysus
versus
the Crucified," we should place the emphasis on that
"versus." We can hear in it an echo of the fierce battle Nietzsche fought and finally lost in his effort to insure the revenge of Dionysus over the Crucified. We can also hear these echoes in
the inhuman aspects of Nietzsche's writing at the time, in the obligation he imposed upon himself to justify even the worst forms of oppression and persecution.
There is a universal wager nowadays against the biblical principle regarded as intrinsically
perverse rather than as perverted by the enormous human ingenuity in the service of this
perversion. This wager cannot be sustained without some form of the sacred, and it has to be
that violent sacred which Nietzsche calls Dionysus. Even though Heidegger also detected the
presence of violence in it, he too glorified the primitive
sacred
. He looked forward to future epiphanies of it and did not anticipate any particular problems with this violence even though
he was writing about this after the end of World War II.
In his later years, Nietzsche kept reviving, glorifying, and modernizing more and more
sinister aspects of the primitive sacred. I am convinced that this process became more
intolerable as it became more radical and led to his final breakdown.
The greatness of Nietzsche is that he committed himself totally to that process and he paid for
his commitment literally with his life. For things to come to such a pass, the forces on both
sides had to be almost evenly balanced. As the prophets would say: "It is a dreadful fate to
fall into the hands of the living God."
Paradoxically, Nietzsche is the one thinker in the modern world whose work did achieve
something that the Christian thinkers have always failed to achieve. They have never dared.
He put his finger on that "sword" that Jesus said he brought, the sword destructive of human culture, that sword no human being can fail to dread and resent even though -- or is it
because? -- it belongs to what Pascal calls
Vordre de la charité
.
This force destroys the old sacred through the revelation of its violent nature, but so far, it has
only managed to wound it, turning it into a fierce monster that now threatens to devour us all.
Mimetic doubles are everywhere in that cosmic battle and it is tempting to see nothing else,
-254-
nothing but empty mimetic rivalry in the opposition between Dionysus and the Crucified.
This is what Heidegger did. Heidegger, here, was still the voice of a modern demystification
that exposes so many false differences that in the end it misses the one and only difference
that is real.
Heidegger fought on the same side as Nietzsche, no doubt, the side of the old sacred, but on
positions less exposed, less forward, less dangerous and revealing than Nietzsche's. He has
succeeded, at least for a while, in neutralizing the "imprudence" of Nietzsche in the domain of religion. With time, it will become easier and easier to realize that, before exploding into
the hands of its maker, this machine was producing the opposite of what it was built for, the
glorification of what is was supposed to vilify, the vilification of what it was supposed to
celebrate.
For quite a few years, I have emphasized the role of collective violence in the genesis of the
primitive sacred and the role of the Bible in the increasing intelligibility of that genesis. My
purpose in the present essay is to show that Nietzsche is deeply but paradoxically involved in
that process.
The present effort will probably meet with skepticism. Many readers will suspect that I am projecting upon Nietzsche a preoccupation too idiosyncratic to yield significant results. This
attempt has to result not in a mutilation of what Nietzsche "really thought" (which does not seem to matter anymore and cannot be reached in any case), but in a revelation of the real
fecundity of Nietzsche's work, his possible contribution to the critical formulae currently
fashionable.
The general reaction to the theme of
the collective murder of God
resembles the
bewilderment and amused condescension that greeted the Nietzschean madman when he
addressed his contemporaries in the market place. This anonymous lunatic
lit a lantern in the bright morning hours, ran to the market and cried incessantly, "I seek God,
I seek God!" As many of those who do not believe in God were standing around just then, he
provoked much laughter. Why, did he get lost? said one. Did he lose his way like a child?
said another. Or is he hiding? Is he afraid of us? Has he gone on a voyage? or emigrated?
Thus they yelled and laughed.
This is the beginning of the most famous text in
The Gay Science
, aphorism 125. Even today,
especially today perhaps, whoever touches upon this untouchable subject,
the collective
murder of God
, finds himself in a position curiously reminiscent of the one described here.
After more than a century, nothing has really changed, especially in those aca-
-255-
demic circles that did not appreciate Nietzsche at the time any more than he appreciated
them.
My readers are too careful with texts, too erudite, attentive, deliberate, thorough, and above
all too shrewd, too good as readers of texts to be scandalized, or ever surprised when they see
me appropriate this text in the informal fashion that I just did. They certainly would not
dispute my right to do this. They have kept in mind the extraordinary similarity of content if
not of form between my somewhat tiresome insistence on the religious significance of the
collective murder and the parallel insistence of this enigmatic text.
Here is the first proclamation of the madman:
"Whither is God," he cried. "I shall tell you. We have killed him -you and I. All of us are his murderers. But how have we done this? How were we able to drink up the sea . . . ?
Since the late eighteenth century, from Jean Paul to Victor Hugo and beyond,
pronouncements regarding the death of God have multiplied with each passing year, and
belated prophets are now forming what is probably the largest crowd ever gathered in our
intellectual history. What everybody has been announcing, of course, is that the biblical god
is dying of old age. It is a more or less natural death in other words.
Most people believe that Nietzsche's text refers exclusively to modern atheism. This is part of
the story, no doubt, but only a part, and an enigmatic part already because it rejects very
pointedly the very notion everybody is trying to find there, the notion of God as something
childish and meaningless really that men gradually learned to do without in the modern age,
as they became more "mature" and learned about electricity, and now computers.
Instead of that gradual fading away of God, with no particular violence or drama, Nietzsche sees the disappearance of God as a horrible murder in which every man is involved: "
We
have killed him
-you and I. All of us are his murderers."
"If God never existed, if there is no such thing as God, how could he be killed?" That is the question only the uninformed reader dares to ask and, as usual with great texts, it is a much
smarter one than all the "informed" philosophical questions.
Gods do not have to exist really in order to be murdered. As a matter of fact, unless they are
first murdered they will never exist. Unlike ordinary beings who can exist only if they are not
murdered, gods begin to exist as gods, at least in the eyes of men, only after they have been
murdered.
In the entire text, the hackneyed expression "God is dead" appears in one passage only, and it is followed by an insistent return upon the theme of the collective murder of God, as if
Nietzsche suddenly realized
-256-
the difference between the hackneyed conception of God's "death" as a spectacle passively
watched and the active deed he had in mind, the collective crime that seems to come from
nowhere.
And he seems to have felt that the collective crime was the more powerful idea but harder to
communicate, an idea indeed that would be resisted and eluded with the utmost energy. More
emphasis was needed, therefore, and Nietzsche provided it, including even a gory description
of the collective murder of God:
God is dead. God remains dead. And we have killed him. How shall we, the murderers of all
murderers, comfort ourselves? What was holiest and most powerful of all that the world has
yet owned has bled to death under our knives. Who will wipe this blood off us? What water is
there for us to clean ourselves? What festivals of atonement, what sacred games shall we
have to invent?
The first two sentences are all we have in that text that resembles the old "God is dead"
theme. But this is enough of an excuse for all the commentators to seize upon it and substitute
once more the harmless cliché for what Nietzsche is really saying. The references to the
blood, and to the knife, and to the wiping of the blood, forcefully take us back to the first
announcement of the madman. God did not die a natural death; he was collectively killed.
And the crime is so great that new festivals of atonement, new sacred games will have to be
invented. New rituals will undoubtedly appear. The consequences of God's murder are
religious, therefore, purely religious. The very deed that seems to put an end to the religious,
process is really the origin of that process, the sum total of it, really, the religious process par
excellence. These new festivals and sacred games will certainly reenact the collective murder
of God. They will be sacrificial rites. The death of God is also his birth.
If God is always the product of his own collective murder, does not this text really say that