Authors: Professor Michael Hardt,Antonio Negri
Tags: #Philosophy, #Political, #Political Science, #General, #American Government
presented as mystifications of, or stand-ins for, the class subjects in
conflict. IfNazi Germany is the ideal type ofthe transformation
ofmodern sovereignty into national sovereignty and ofits articula-
tion in capitalist form, then Stalinist Russia is the ideal type of the
transformation of popular interest and the cruel logics that follow
from it into a project of national modernization, mobilizing for
its own purposes the productive forces that yearn for liberation
from capitalism.
Here we could analyze the national socialist apotheosis ofthe
modern concept ofsovereignty and its transformation into national
sovereignty: nothing could more clearly demonstrate the coherence
ofthis passage than the transfer ofpower from the Prussian monarchy
to Hitler’s regime, under the good auspices ofthe German bourgeoi-
sie. This passage, however, is well known, as are the explosive
violence ofthis transfer ofpower, the exemplary obedience ofthe
German people, their military and civil valor in the service ofthe
nation, and the secondary consequences that we can call, in a
kind ofintellectual shorthand, Auschwitz (as symbol ofthe Jewish
holocaust) and Buchenwald (as symbol ofthe extermination of
communists, homosexuals, Gypsies, and others). Let us leave this
story to other scholars and to the disgrace ofhistory.
We are more interested here with the other side ofthe national
question in Europe during this era. In other words, what really
S O V E R E I G N T Y O F T H E N A T I O N - S T A T E
111
happened when nationalism went hand in hand with socialism in
Europe? In order to respond to this question, we have to revisit a
few central moments in the history of European socialism. In partic-
ular, we must remember that not long after its inception, between
the middle and end ofthe nineteenth century, the socialist Interna-
tional had to come to terms with strong nationalist movements,
and through this confrontation the original internationalist passion
ofthe workers’ movement quickly evaporated. The policies of
the strongest European workers’ movements, in Germany, Austria,
France, and above all England, immediately raised the banner of
national interest. Social-democratic reformism was entirely invested
in this compromise conceived in the name ofthe nation—a com-
promise between class interests, that is, between the proletariat and
certain strata ofthe bourgeois hegemonic structure in each country.
Let’s not even talk about the ignoble history ofbetrayal in which
segments ofthe European workers’ movement supported the impe-
rialist enterprises ofthe European nation-states, nor the unpardon-
able folly that brought together the various European reformisms
in consenting to the masses’ being led to slaughter in the First
World War.
Social-democratic reformism did have an adequate theory for
these positions. Several Austrian social-democratic professors in-
vented it, contemporaries ofMusil’s Count Leinsdorf. In the idyllic
atmosphere ofalpine Kakania, in the gentle intellectual climate of
that ‘‘return to Kant,’’ those professors, such as Otto Bauer, insisted
on the necessity ofconsidering nationality a fundamental element of
modernization.33 In fact, they believed that from the confrontation
between nationality (defined as a community ofcharacter) and
capitalist development (understood as society) there would emerge
a dialectic that in its unfolding would eventually favor the proletariat
and its progressive hegemony in society. This program ignored the
fact that the concept of nation-state is not divisible but rather
organic, not transcendental but transcendent, and even in its tran-
scendence it is constructed to oppose every tendency on the part
ofthe proletariat to reappropriate social spaces and social wealth.
What, then, could modernization mean ifit is fundamentally tied
112
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
to the reform of the capitalist system and inimical to any opening
ofthe revolutionary process? These authors celebrated the nation
without wanting to pay the price ofthis celebration. Or better,
they celebrated it while mystifying the destructive power of the
concept ofnation. Given this perspective, support for the imperialist
projects and the interimperialist war were really logical and inevita-
ble positions for social-democratic reformism.
Bolshevism, too, entered the terrain ofnationalist mythology,
particularly through Stalin’s celebrated prerevolutionary pamphlet
on Marxism and the national question.34 According to Stalin, nations
are immediately revolutionary, and revolution means moderniza-
tion: nationalism is an ineluctable stage in development. Through
Stalin’s translation, however, as nationalism becomes socialist, so-
cialism becomes Russian, and Ivan the Terrible is laid to rest in
the tomb beside Lenin. The Communist International is transformed
into an assembly ofthe ‘‘fifth column’’ ofRussian national interests.
The notion ofcommunist revolution—the deterritorializing specter
that had haunted Europe and the world, and that from the Paris
Commune to 1917 in Saint Petersburg and to Mao’s Long March
had managed to bring together deserters, internationalist partisans,
striking workers, and cosmopolitan intellectuals—was finally made
into a reterritorializing regime ofnational sovereignty. It is a tragic
irony that nationalist socialism in Europe came to resemble national
socialism. This is not because ‘‘the two extremes meet,’’ as some
liberals would like to think, but because the abstract machine of
national sovereignty is at the heart ofboth.
When, in the midst ofthe cold war, the concept oftotalitarian-
ism was introduced into political science, it only touched on extrin-
sic elements ofthe question. In its most coherent form the concept
oftotalitarianism was used to denounce the destruction ofthe
democratic public sphere, the continuation ofJacobinist ideologies,
the extreme forms ofracist nationalism, and the negation ofmarket
forces. The concept of totalitarianism, however, ought to delve
much more deeply into the real phenomena and at the same time
give a better explanation ofthem. In fact, totalitarianism consists
S O V E R E I G N T Y O F T H E N A T I O N - S T A T E
113
not simply in totalizing the effects of social life and subordinating
them to a global disciplinary norm, but also in the negation ofsocial
life itself, the erosion of its foundation, and the theoretical and
practical stripping away ofthe very possibility ofthe existence of
the multitude. What is totalitarian is the organic foundation and
the unified source ofsociety and the state. The community is not
a dynamic collective creation but a primordial founding myth. An
originary notion ofthe people poses an identity that homogenizes
and purifies the image ofthe population while blocking the con-
structive interactions of differences within the multitude.
Sieyès saw the embryo oftotalitarianism already in eighteenth-
century conceptions ofnational and popular sovereignty, concep-
tions that effectively preserved the absolute power of monarchy
and transferred it to national sovereignty. He glimpsed the future
ofwhat might be called totalitarian democracy.35 In the debate over
the Constitution ofYear III ofthe French Revolution, Sieyès
denounced the ‘‘bad plans for a re-total [
re´-total
] instead ofa republic [
re´-publique
], which would be fatal for freedom and ruinous for both the public realm and the private.’’36 The concept ofnation
and the practices ofnationalism are from the beginning set down
on the road not to the republic but to the ‘‘re-total,’’ the total thing,
that is, the totalitarian overcoding ofsocial life.
2.3
T H E D I A L E C T I C S O F
C O L O N I A L S O V E R E I G N T Y
To Toussaint l’Ouverture
Toussaint, the most unhappy man ofmen!
Whether the whistling Rustic tend his plough
Within thy hearing, or thy head be now
Pillowed in some deep dungeon’s earless den;—
O miserable Chieftain! where and when
Wilt thou find patience! Yet die not; do thou
Wear rather in thy bonds a cheerful brow:
Though fallen thyself, never to rise again,
Live, and take comfort. Thou hast left behind
Powers that will work for thee; air, earth, and skies;
There’s not a breathing ofthe common wind
That will forget thee; thou hast great allies;
Thy friends are exultations, agonies,
And love, and man’s unconquerable mind.
William Wordsworth
We now need to take a step back and examine the
genealogy ofthe concept ofsovereignty from the perspective of
colonialism. The crisis ofmodernity has from the beginning had an
intimate relation to racial subordination and colonization. Whereas
within its domain the nation-state and its attendant ideological
structures work tirelessly to create and reproduce the purity ofthe
people, on the outside the nation-state is a machine that produces
Others, creates racial difference, and raises boundaries that delimit
and support the modern subject ofsovereignty. These boundaries
T H E D I A L E C T I C S O F C O L O N I A L S O V E R E I G N T Y
115
and barriers, however, are not impermeable but rather serve to
regulate two-way flows between Europe and its outside. The Orien-
tal, the African, the Amerindian are all necessary components for the
negative foundation of European identity and modern sovereignty as
such. The dark Other ofEuropean Enlightenment stands as its
very foundation just as the productive relationship with the ‘‘dark
continents’’ serves as the economic foundation of the European
nation-states.1 The racial conflict intrinsic to European modernity
is another symptom ofthe permanent crisis that defines modern
sovereignty. The colony stands in dialectical opposition to European
modernity, as its necessary double and irrepressible antagonist. Colo-
nial sovereignty is another insufficient attempt to resolve the crisis
ofmodernity.
Humankind Is Oneand Many
The age ofEuropean discovery and the progressively intense com-
munication among the spaces and peoples ofthe earth that followed
have always carried with them a real utopian element. But so much
blood has been spilled, so many lives and cultures destroyed, that
it seems much more urgent to denounce the barbarity and horror
ofwestern European (and then also U.S., Soviet, and Japanese)
expansion and control over the globe. We think it important,
however, not to forget the utopian tendencies that have always
accompanied the progression toward globalization, even ifthese
tendencies have continually been defeated by the powers of modern
sovereignty. The love of differences and the belief in the universal
freedom and equality of humanity proper to the revolutionary
thought ofRenaissance humanism reappear here on a global scale.
This utopian element ofglobalization is what prevents us from
simply falling back into particularism and isolationism in reaction
to the totalizing forces of imperialism and racist domination, pushing
us instead to forge a project of counterglobalization, counter-
Empire. This utopian moment, however, has never been unambigu-
ous. It is a tendency that constantly conflicts with sovereign order
and domination. We see three exemplary expressions ofthis utopi-
116
P A S S A G E S O F S O V E R E I G N T Y
anism, in all its ambiguity, in the thought ofBartolome´ de Las
Casas, Toussaint L’Ouverture, and Karl Marx.
In the first half-century after the European landing in the
Americas at Hispaniola, Bartolome´ de Las Casas witnessed with
horror the barbarity ofthe conquistadores and colonists and their
enslavement and genocide ofthe Amerindians. The majority ofthe
Spanish military, administrators, and colonists, hungry for gold and
power, saw the occupants ofthis new world as irrevocably Other,
less than human, or at least naturally subordinate to Europeans—and
Las Casas recounts for us how the newly arrived Europeans treated
them worse than their animals. In this context it is a wonder that
Las Casas, who was part ofthe Spanish mission, could separate
himselfenough from the common stream ofopinion to insist on
the humanity ofthe Amerindians and contest the brutality ofthe
Spanish rulers. His protest arises from one simple principle:
human-
kind is one and equal.
One should recognize at the same time, however, that a mis-
sionary vocation is intrinsically linked to the humanitarian project
ofthe good bishop ofChiapas. In fact, Las Casas can think equality
only in terms ofsameness. The Amerindians are equal to Europeans
in nature only insofar as they are potentially European, or really
potentially Christian: ‘‘The nature ofmen is the same and all are
called by Christ in the same way.’’2 Las Casas cannot see beyond
the Eurocentric view ofthe Americas, in which the highest generos-