Read Critical thinking for Students Online

Authors: Roy van den Brink-Budgen

Critical thinking for Students (13 page)

 
 
 
 
ANALOGIES, HYPOTHESES, DEFINITIONS AND PRINCIPLES
 
ANALOGIES
 

In 2006, a UK judge refused to impose an antisocial behaviour order on a man who was growing cannabis at his home. The local council had applied for the order and for possession of the man’s council house. The judge threw the case out, making the point that cultivating cannabis is ‘no worse than having tomato plants’. He explained that he couldn’t see how growing cannabis could ever be seen as a nuisance because, for the neighbours, it’s no different to them than if tomato plants had been grown.

 

The judge’s argument is an interesting one. What he does is to use one line of reasoning. This is to say that ‘if growing tomatoes is not seen as a nuisance, then neither is growing cannabis’. As you can see, he is not making any judgement of whether or not smoking cannabis (or selling it to others) is acceptable. His comment is only about growing it.

 

The judge is using what we call an
analogy
. This is a common form of argument. In essence, it amounts to using an evidence-claim. In this example, the judge takes the evidence-claim that tomato-growing is not seen as a nuisance. Because, he argues, this is the case, we can infer from this that growing other things sufficiently similar to tomatoes is acceptable. Since growing cannabis is sufficiently similar, then it is acceptable to grow it.

 

We could represent the argument as a syllogism.

 

Growing tomatoes is not a nuisance to neighbours.

 

Growing cannabis is the same as growing tomatoes.

 

Therefore growing cannabis is not a nuisance to neighbours.

 

As with our previous examination of a syllogism,
if
the reasons are true, then so is the conclusion, making this argument a valid one.

 

In any evaluation of an analogy, we have to consider the degree of similarity between the two parts. This will be particularly significant when, as in the judge’s argument, an argument based only on an analogy stands or falls depending on this degree of similarity.

 

The organisation Christian Aid ran a campaign in 2009 in which they claimed ‘For every excuse not to end poverty, we have 10 bright ideas why we can’. One of these was an analogy. (You should be able to evaluate two of the other ‘bright ideas’, in the light of what we were doing in the previous section on ‘appeals’ – ‘Over 70% of us think poverty eradication is important’, and ‘the United Nations Secretary-General has categorically stated that it can happen’.)

 

The ‘bright idea’ analogy was ‘it’s a big task, but no bigger than ending slavery and putting a man on the moon’. Just like the tomatoes and cannabis analogy, the claim here is one of similarity: that the achievement of these two big things shows that we can achieve this other big thing. If we put it into an argument form, we get the following:

 

The abolition of slavery was achieved. A man was put on the moon. These two things were both very difficult to achieve. Therefore the abolition of poverty can be achieved.

 

You will probably see that there’s a big assumption needed in this argument. This is that ‘the abolition of poverty is no more difficult than was ending slavery and putting a man on the moon’. In any analogy we always have this assumption of sufficient similarity. Without it, the argument cannot work.

 

So our task is to see if this assumption can be supported. The first problem is that, unfortunately, slavery has not been ended. The Anti-Slavery Society makes the point that, though slavery as we normally think of it was abolished in the nineteenth century, it is still practised in various parts of the world today (including Africa). Though the number of slaves is disputed, depending on the definition used, the estimates put the number at around 3 million upwards.

 

With regard to putting a man on the moon, this was (as most people would accept) achieved in 1969. However, it might be argued that, though it was very difficult and so a hugely impressive scientific and technological achievement, it was not as difficult as ending poverty. For one thing, it did not depend on the co-operation of the government of every country in the world (which ending poverty would). For another thing, the definition of ‘putting a man on the moon’ is a straightforward one. The definition of ‘poverty’ is anything but simple: if poverty is ended, does no one go hungry any more? Do certain diseases disappear? Is all housing at least adequate? And yet another thing: would the ending of poverty require a huge redistribution of wealth away from the rich to the poor both between and within countries? Would people like Roman Abramovich agree? Would the Saudi Royal Family agree?

 

Our problem, as we have seen, is that ending poverty is certainly a bigger (and less clear-cut) task than putting a man on the moon. In addition, in that slavery hasn’t yet been abolished, we can’t say whether it
can
be abolished (and thus whether the difficulty-level of its abolition is sufficiently similar to that of ending poverty). As a result, since the analogy (or, more accurately, the analogies) does (do) not work well, the argument falls. (This last point, of course, refers to an argument like the tomatoes and cannabis one in which the analogy is the only reason. If it is only one of at least two, then the argument might still stand.)

 

We have seen with our fairly detailed analysis that we need to treat analogies in the same way that we treat any other evidence-claim. Is the analogy relevant? Is it sufficient for the argument? To do this, we need to focus on similarities and dissimilarities.

 

What follows is a detailed look at an analogy, by going through an evaluation step by step. The argument is one used by someone who was head of the UK’s Youth Justice Board.

 

Locking up children who commit crimes is like building more coal-fired power stations. You create future problems by doing so. Therefore we should lock up far fewer young people than we presently do.

 

What is the analogy?

 

This analogy compares the problems that will follow putting children who commit crimes in prison with those that will follow building more coal-fired power stations.

 

What is its function in the argument?

 

It provides the only reason for the conclusion that we should lock up far fewer young people than we do.

 

Does the analogy work?

 

As we have seen, answering this question involves asking other ones:

 

What are the significant similarities between the situations?

 

• Building coal-fired power stations could create future problems in terms of using up resources. Locking up young criminals might create future criminals which will then be a drain on the nation’s resources. (Consider the use of the term ‘resources’.)

 

• Building coal-fired power stations provides a short-term benefit as does locking up young criminals (electricity + security) but the trade-off for the future brings possible problems (pollution/resentment +…).

 

• In each case there are alternatives which might have both short- and long-term advantages, thereby avoiding the disadvantages. (Nuclear power/non-custodial sentences; wind power/fines or…?)

 

What are the significant differences between the situations?

 

• Building coal-fired power stations presumably creates future health problems in terms of pollution. Locking up young criminals might create future criminals but these are not necessarily a threat to health as such (possibly more to
property
). Indeed, the evidence suggests that most young offenders have stopped
offending
by the time they’re 25 anyway.

 

• Building coal-fired power stations could create future problems in terms of using up scarce resources. Locking up young criminals might create future criminals but these will not be a depletion of non-renewable resources.

 

• Building coal-fired power stations is not something that can be easily changed in the short-term. Putting young criminals in prison can be supplemented quickly by community programmes.

 

Are there any other aspects of the analogy that need to be considered?

 

The two situations are similar (although not in the way the author intends) by both providing benefits. Coal-fired power stations provide electricity, and prisons provide security for the public. Both provide employment. Both provide investment in the future (reformed criminals and industrial etc. progress.) In this way, the support which the analogy gives to the conclusion is lessened.

 

Which of the two is greater – the similarities or the differences? This is a difficult question to answer and we might disagree. I think that, on balance, the differences are greater but there are very interesting similarities. In that the argument relies only on the analogy, the argument is therefore vulnerable to the charge that there are important differences between the two.

 

It needs to be remembered that, when someone is using an analogy in an argument, we can’t respond by saying ‘you can’t say that: the two things aren’t the same’. Of course, they’re not
the same
. If they were the same, there wouldn’t be an analogy!

 

Locking up children who commit crimes is like putting children in prison.

 

All we have is a circular relationship, not an analogy.

 

Sometimes you’ll come across a different version of using an analogy.

 

People should expect that some space missions don’t succeed. Putting a spacecraft safely on Mars is hard and risky. It’s not a trip to Grandma’s house. (NASA May 2008)

 

In this example, we have NASA using what’s called a disanalogy. As you can see, this takes the negative form of an analogy: this is not like that, so…

 

You might like to look at this disanalogy in the same way that we looked at the analogy on children in prisons (comparing the similarities and dissimilarities), but this time looking to see if the dissimilarities outweigh the similarities. However many you find on either side, it’s pretty clear that they will. In this example, the disanalogy is part of an argument in which it isn’t just a question of an analogy-type reason being used as the reason to draw the conclusion. The argument can be seen in the following way: 

 

(R) Putting a spacecraft safely on Mars is hard and risky.

 

(IC) It’s not a trip to Grandma’s house.

 

(C) People should expect that some space missions don’t succeed.

 

You can see that, in this argument, the disanalogy is not necessary for the argument. If it wasn’t there, the conclusion could still be drawn. (You might have spotted the assumption that ‘trips to Grandma’s house normally succeed’.)

 

Using analogies is, in an important way, yet another example of the importance of consistency in argument. Someone using an analogy in an argument is saying ‘here’s one situation in which
x
is the case; here’s another in which
x
also applies/follows/exists, so we should do the same in both situations’. Any demonstration that the two situations are not sufficiently similar weakens this argument for consistency. (With a disanalogy, of course, the process is the other way round: the more similar the two situations are, the less powerful is the argument for inconsistency.)

 
HYPOTHESES
 

We can also see analogous reasoning as an example of a particular type of reasoning. The author is saying ‘if this happens in a given situation, then the same thing should happen in the other situation.’ This type of reasoning is called
hypothetical
reasoning
. However it is expressed, it will have an
if

then
form. (It could, for example, be ‘were this to be the case, then …’) We’ll now look at such reasoning in more detail.

 

You will remember that we saw an example of this type of reasoning when we looked at slippery slopes. We saw there that there was a problem with the move from the first ‘if’ to the final ‘then’, as shown in the example we looked at.

 

If you think girls should be taught positive female role models, then you must think that they should be taught to see men in a negative light … so you must think that they can kill men.

 

This showed that with hypothetical reasoning, the connections do need to be justified (as with the controlled climb). Let’s look to see if we can use hypothetical reasoning to go somewhere undesirable but in a justified way, rather than slithering down a slippery slope.

 

The United Nations (UN) warned in 2009 that the population of the world (6.7 billion) would double in the next 40 years if growth rates don’t decline. If the world’s population did indeed double by the middle of the century, then there would be massive problems of famine, disease, and frequent conflicts over scarce resources, especially water. It is therefore vitally important to look at ways of slowing the growth of population.

 

As you can see, there are two hypothetical parts of the argument. The first sentence is the first part, and shows that the form of the hypothetical is sometimes reversed (
x
, if
y
). The second sentence is the second hypothetical. The conclusion is drawn from both of them. You can see that the conclusion is justified all the way. (Of course, this does not mean that there aren’t assumed steps in the argument. A crucial one sits between the second reason and the conclusion: ‘solutions to food and other shortages will not be found’. For example it could be that scientists will be able to create food crops which need little water.)

 

You will have seen that hypothetical reasoning, when it extends from one such reason to another, is like a chain, with the links connecting in a necessary way to the conclusion. Not surprisingly, then, they are sometimes called ‘chain arguments’. Here’s another one on the same subject of the problems of population growth:

 

The Health and Family Welfare Minister of India, Mr Ghulam Nabi Azad, has called for massive efforts to be made to bring electricity to all of the population of India in order to slow down his country’s potentially catastrophic population growth. If electricity is made available to all areas (including rural areas), then both electric light and television could be in all homes. ‘If there is electricity in every village,’ Mr Azad argues, ‘then people will watch TV till late at night and then fall asleep. They won’t get a chance to produce children.’ Mr Azad claims that ‘80 per cent of population growth can be reduced through TV.’ Therefore bringing electricity to all homes in India will solve the problem of population growth.

 

You can see the way that the chain is created. We can focus on it by labelling each section:

 

• If A (electricity in all areas), then B (electric light and TV in all homes).

 

• If B, then C (people will watch TV until late, then fall asleep).

 

• If C, then D (people won’t get a chance to produce children).

 

• Therefore, if A, then D.

 

Though we might want to evaluate the argument (in terms of possible issues with C and D), the chain sequence is clear. In case you spotted the assumption between B and C that ‘the TV programmes would be good enough to keep people watching’, Mr Azad has got there before you, calling for India’s TV channels to provide high-quality programmes.

 

Having seen hypothetical arguments in action, it is time to enter a cautionary note. Look at the next example:

 

Herbal remedies are regarded as less toxic and more natural than drugs prescribed by doctors. But we need to remember that, if herbal remedies work, they must be drugs, and if they are drugs, they must have side-effects. Therefore people need to be told that herbal remedies will have side-effects in the same way as any prescribed drug.

 

You will have noticed the hypothetical argument-chain in the second sentence. There is no problem with this: if A, then B; if B, then C. What should have followed was if A, then D: if herbal remedies work, then (people need to be told) they will have
side-effects
. Instead, this link in the chain is missing. The author draws a conclusion which is not in a hypothetical form. Given that the rest of the argument is in this form, this should not be done. Perhaps herbal remedies don’t work after all, in which case the conclusion cannot be drawn.

 

So it is important to remember that reasons that are no more than hypothetical require a hypothetical conclusion.

 

There’s another point to mention. We have seen that hypothetical arguments use a form of ‘if … then’ reasoning. But this does not mean that every time we see an ‘if’, we’ve found some hypothetical reasoning.

 

We can’t say if the world’s population will continue to grow at the present rate. There are too many variables to have to consider. Therefore we must plan for both large and smaller population increases.

 

You can see that, in this example, the ‘if’ is not part of a hypothetical, in that there’s no ‘then’ that follows it.

 

Other books

Unforgiven (Wanderers #3) by Jessica Miller
Gun Church by Reed Farrel Coleman
Reese by Terri Anne Browning
Faithful in Pleasure by Lacey Thorn
Blue by Danielle Steel
Seeing Black by Sidney Halston
Black Box by Ivan Turner
Just Killing Time by Julianne Holmes
Girls In 3-B, The by Valerie Taylor
So Much More by Adams, Elizabeth


readsbookonline.com Copyright 2016 - 2024